SankarAcArya, following the upanishads,
asserts that the sole cause of the universe is the One brahman that is really
nirguNa. The problem with asserting One brahman that is without parts,
changeless and eternal, as the only cause of the universe is this - the
universe is normally perceived to be full of many separate parts which change
all the time, and has little that is eternal in it. How is it that the
changeless and non-relational brahman produces the variegated universe? This
is related to the larger philosophical problem of change and continuity, which
had historically played such a big role in Indian thinking that many buddhist
schools had denied that an eternal entity like brahman could even exist.
Moreover, in the buddhist schools, the notion of an Atman is itself an
erroneous concept, because everything was defined to be momentary.
Among the brahminical schools, the nyAya and vaiSeshika schools handled the
problem of change by postulating atoms (aNus) as the unit constituents
of any entity. Transformation and change were explained by means of
combinations of integral numbers of atoms (dvayaNuka, trayaNuka
etc.), and the individual Atman was also supposed to be atomic in size
and qualities. A creator God (ISvara) was arrived at by an inferential
argument, on the premise that everything must have a cause of some sort, so
that the cause of the universe is God. This inferred ISvara was then
identified with the brahman of the vedas. The yoga and sAm.khya schools
postulated ultimate reality to be a duality of purusha and
prakRti. The purusha was said to be changeless and the one
undergoing bondage and liberation owing to contact with or withdrawal from
prakRti. All change was then described as the working of
prakRti, which deluded the purusha into activity and thus into
bondage (bandha). Liberation (moksha) for the purusha
arose only when the purusha dissociated completely from the workings of
prakRti. Meanwhile, the position of a creator God remained ambivalent
in the sAm.khya system. Most classical sAm.khya authors denied the necessity
of an ISvara, while some were willing to postulate ISvara as an
eternally liberated purusha. The yoga system, as expounded in the
yoga-sUtras of patanjali, accepted ISvara and made
ISvara-praNidhana an essential aspect of yogic sAdhana.
The pUrva mImAm.sA system was concerned primarily with asserting the
eternal value of the vedas, and interpreted everything in the vedas in the
context of ritual action. Consequently, impelling the listener to action was
asserted to be the over-riding purpose of the vedas. The fruit of the ritual
action was also mentioned in the same vedas, and the highest fruit that was
obtainable by the proper performance of ritual action was heaven. On this view,
the individual Atman attained heaven by the performance of Vedic ritual, and
returned to the cycle of rebirths otherwise. On the other hand, the
aupanishada tradition which gave birth to the mature vedAnta systems
asserted an eternal Atman forcefully. This Atman was also held to be beyond
birth and death. Physical death only meant that the Atman took another body.
Moreover, the upanishads declare the Atman to
be ultimately the same as the One brahman which is the sole cause of the
universe.
The upanishads relate a higher vision that is mystic and that does
not demand to be logically substantiated. The problem of the one brahman
creating the diverse universe was handled by means of various analogies, as in
the chAndogya upanishad. The nature of the Indian philosophical traditions,
however, required every new teacher to not only relate his vision of reality,
but also to substantiate it by logical arguments. The naiyyAyikas, the
buddhists and the grammarians had developed methods of logical analysis,
including inducto-deductive reasoning, evaluating the validity of cognitions
with a consistent theory of language and meaning, and rigorous requirements of
consistency and non-contradiction. Analogies did play an important part in the
logical analysis, but the spirit of the times called for more intellectual
speculation and rationalization. This was the prime motivation for
bAdarAyaNa's brahmasUtras, which attempted to harmonize the many teachings of
the upanishads into one consistent system. The brahmasUtras are therefore
called the nyAya-prasthAna (not to be confused with the independent
philosophical system of the nyAya).
The gauDapAdIya kArikAs and Sankara's bhAshyas follow in the same spirit. In
establishing the main tenets of advaita vedAnta,
Sankara drew upon mImAm.sA theories of perception and language, and sAm.khya
notions of the transformations of prakRti. He also gave a place for
yogic practice in his system, and used nyAya methods of inferential reasoning
wherever appropriate. This was coupled with a critique of the logical
shortcomings of these systems and rejecting those tenets which were not in
accordance with the thought of the upanishads. Thus, for example, he accepted
mImAm.sA rules of exegesis, but pointed out that their applicability was
limited largely to the karma-kANDa, the upanishads requiring different methods
of interpretation. Similarly, he denied an independent existence to the
sAm.khyan prakRti, and in his analysis of the relation of the universe
to brahman, made the equivalent mAyA completely dependent upon the
reality of brahman. maNDAna miSra, Sankara's
contemporary, also developed powerful arguments that denied ultimate reality
to difference. Between Sankara and maNDana, advaita vedAnta became the most
important school of vedAnta, and indeed of all Indian philosophical thought.
However, after this time, the followers of rival schools started re-evaluating
their positions, modifying their views and began posing new objections to
advaita. The later teachers in the advaita tradition lived and worked in such
a milieu.
Among the works of Sankara's immediate disciples (8th century CE), toTaka's SrutisArasamuddhAraNa did not
attract sub-commentaries from later authors, while no texts attributed to hastAmalaka were widely known. sureSvara's upanishad-bhAshya-vArttikAs and
the naishkarmayasiddhi, and padmapAda's pancapAdikA influenced the course of post-Sankaran
advaita vedAnta significantly. Soon after their time, vAcaspati miSra (9th century CE), wrote his bhAmatI
commentary on Sankara's brahmasUtra bhAshya, and prakASAtman (10th century CE) wrote a vivaraNa to the pancapAdikA.
Later authors sometimes wrote independent treatises of their own, but more
often chose an earlier text to comment upon, thus building up sets of
commentaries and sub-commentaries, which make the philosophical views of the
sub-schools clearer. These authors may be classified under four heads for the
sake of convenience -
Both the bhAmatI and vivaraNa lines base themselves upon
differing interpretations of SankarAcArya's brahmasUtra bhAshya. Since the
brahmasUtras continued to be the defining source for all vedAnta schools, the
bhAmatI and vivaraNa schools attained the most prominence in the
dialogue that developed between advaita and rival vedAnta schools on the one
hand, and advaita vedAnta and non-vedAnta schools on the other.
Last updated on May 5, 1999.
The advaita home page |